Monday, July 15, 2019

Gal and Rucker (2018) on the Loss of Loss Aversion

David Gal and Derek D. Rucker, “The Loss of Loss Aversion: Will It Loom Larger Than Its Gain?” Journal of Consumer Psychology 28(3): 497-516, July 2018.

• Social scientists seem to all but universally believe in loss aversion, the notion that losses “loom larger” psychologically than do similarly-sized gains.

 Gal and Rucker claim that the actual evidence does not support any general tendency for losses to loom larger than gains: everything depends upon the context.

• There’s a bit of circularity in the promotion of loss aversion: some phenomenon (like the equity premium puzzle or the endowment effect) is “explained” by loss aversion, and then the existence of the phenomenon (the equity premium, the endowment effect) is taken to be evidence that loss aversion is pervasive. 

• The status quo bias might reflect a preference towards inaction – and such a preference can exist in the absence of loss aversion, due to the lack of a motive for action, or economizing on processing costs, or the tendency to regret errors of commission more than errors of omission. 

 When asked to trade their original good for an essentially identical one, loss aversion is not implicated – but people still show a large status quo bias. Action v. inaction confounds the loss-gain story. 

 Is the endowment effect just a case of a status quo bias, and therefore does not require loss aversion? 

 The “retention paradigm” recasts endowment effect experiments as willingness-to-pay (WTP) to obtain an item v. WTP to retain an item – so now the “inaction” choice is not to have the good in both cases. (That is, the confounding of loss aversion with inaction is sidestepped.) 

 If loss aversion is active, then in the retention paradigm, the WTP to retain will be higher than the WTP to obtain. But in the experiments, there was no premium to retain a good or service. For “mundane” goods – mugs, notebooks – obtaining tended to have a higher WTP than retaining. 

 One has to be creative to come up with reasonable “retain” scenarios! Fixing a broken phone, perhaps? 

 Analogous experiments ask if you would like to receive $0 for a good you own, or exchange it for another good. The second condition swaps the owned and alternative good. Mug v. $5 shows no endowment effect – even though the standard exchange paradigm (that is, not the "retention" paradigm) with these goods shows a significant endowment effect. 

 For the standard “loss aversion ratio” test, not accepting the bet is the status quo. This test, too, can be recast: Would you rather receive $0 with a probability of 1 or take a 50-50 bet with the possibility of winning or losing $15? People seem to have a slight preference for the risky alternative. 

 When stakes are higher, preferences shift toward the sure thing – but this could reflect risk aversion, not loss aversion. (And, loss aversion is generally taken to be independent of the stakes.) 

 When you ask people directly about the psychological impact of winning or losing something  you ask them how they feel about these events  losing doesn't dominate in terms of the magnitude of feelings. How do you feel about losing a mug versus winning a mug? 

 How do you feel about losing $3 versus winning $3? What about $100? At the low stakes, people seem to care more about the gain. 

 Loss “frames” are not generally more motivating than “gain” frames (despite some evidence to the contrary in certain domains). 

 Why is loss aversion so popular given its questionable evidentiary base? Perhaps in part due to a status-quo bias among researchers(!), or confirmation bias within Kuhnian “normal science.” 

 Loss aversion holds intuitive appeal: we all feel some losses acutely. And the name “loss aversion” itself is persuasive.

No comments:

Post a Comment